transcendental
1. Philosophy. Concerned with the a priori or intuitive basis of
knowledge as independent of experience. Asserting a fundamental
irrationality or supernatural element in experience.
2. Beyond common thought or experience; mystical or supernatural.
(trânscendere trans- + scandere, to climb)
transcendentalism
... in philosophy, term describing systems holding that there are
modes of being beyond the reach of mundane experience. It is closely
associated with Kant, who states that transcendental
elements of thought (such as concepts of space and time and
categories of judgment) cannot be perceived directly through
experience; nevertheless, they add to empirical knowledge. He called
these elements noumena (as opposed to phenomena).
(trânscendere : trâns-, trans- + scandere, to climb)
metaphysics
1. Philosophy. The branch of philosophy that examines the nature of
reality, including the relationship between mind and matter,
substance and attribute, fact and value.
2. A priori speculation upon questions that
are unanswerable to scientific observation, analysis, or
experiment.
(Ta meta ta phusika, (the things) after the physics, the title of
Aristotle's treatise on
first principles (so called because it followed his work on physics);
meta, after; phusikos, of nature, from phusis, nature)
3. Ontology (the study of the nature of
being), cosmology, and philosophical theology are its main branches.
The term comes from the metaphysical treatises of Aristotle
, who presented the First Philosophy (as he called it) after the
Physics - meta-physic = after physics.
a priori
1. Proceeding from a known or assumed cause to a necessarily related
effect; deductive.
2. Based on a hypothesis or theory rather than on experiment or
experience.
3. Made before or without examination; not supported by factual
study.
(â priorì: â, from + priorì, former)
ontology
The branch of metaphysics that deals with
the nature of being.
(on, ont-, present participle of einai, to be)
materialism
1. Philosophy. The theory that physical matter is the only reality
and that everything, including thought, feeling, mind, and will, can
be explained in terms of matter and physical phenomena.
2. The theory or doctrine that physical well-being and worldly
possessions constitute the greatest good and highest value in
life.
(mâteria, matter)
(1) A proposition, or a statement, is factually meaningful only if it is verifiable. This is understood in the sense that the proposition can be judged probable from experience, not in the sense that its truth can be conclusively established by experience.
(2) A proposition is verifiable only if it is either an experiential proposition or one from which some experiential proposition can be deduced in conjunction with other premises.
(3) A proposition is formally meaningful only if it is true by virtue of the definitions of its terms--that is, tautologous.
(4) The laws of logic and mathematics are all tautologous.
(5) A proposition is literally meaningful only if it is either verifiable or tautologous.
(6) Since metaphysical statements are neither verifiable nor tautologous, they are literally meaningless.
(7) Since ethical, aesthetical, and theological statements also fail to meet the same conditions, they too are cognitively meaningless--although they may possess "emotive" meaning.
(8) Since metaphysics, ethics, philosophy of religion, and aesthetics are all eliminated, the only tasks of philosophy are clarification and analysis. Thus, the propositions of philosophy are linguistic, not factual, and philosophy is a department of logic.
The Vienna Circle disintegrated in the late 1930s after the Nazis took Austria, but its influence spread throughout Europe and America, and its concept continues in the modern emphasis on the analysis of language as a function of philosophy.
...is a major kind of reasoning process in which a conclusion is
drawn from particular cases. In inductive reasoning there is no
logical movement from premises to conclusion. The premises
constitute good reasons for accepting the conclusion.
The premises in inductive reasoning are usually based on facts
or observations. There is always a possibility, though, that
the premises may be true while the conclusion is false, since there
is not necessarily a logical relationship between premises and
conclusion.
For example, a child growing up in a community where only English is
spoken may wrongly conclude by induction that everyone in the world
speaks English.
Inductive reasoning plays a very important role in our acquisition of knowledge about the world. Practically all our scientific and practical knowledge is based on induction. Past experience is used as the basis for generalizing about future experience.
David HUME pointed out
what is now called the problem of induction, namely, that the
results of the inductive processes are always in doubt,
because one cannot justify the movement to the conclusion, and the
conclusion can turn out to be false.
There has been a great deal of work in the last 200 years in the
philosophy of science to find some solution to Hume's analysis-some
way of justifying inductive procedures. This type of study continues
because, Hume's arguments notwithstanding, inductive reasoning is
essential to science, law, and other fields of knowledge.
What is called mathematical induction is actually not a form of induction at all; rather, it is a special kind of deductive mathematical reasoning process.
...is a method of logical reasoning, as well as the
conclusion reached by use of such a method. The deductive method is
the method of proof that is used in any situation for which there
exists a set of underlying assumptions (axioms or postulates).
Any conclusion reached by the deductive method, however, must be
true in all circumstances in which the assumptions are true.
In each area of knowledge that has a set of underlying assumptions, the deductive method is used to discover as many consequences as possible. If some of the consequences do not fit the observations, then revisions of the assumptions are considered in an effort to make the theoretical consequences compatible with the observations.
One of the most distinctive of Aristotle's philosophic contributions was a new notion of causality. Each thing or event, he thought, has more than one "reason" that helps to explain what, why, and where it is. Earlier Greek thinkers had tended to assume that only one sort of cause can be really explanatory; Aristotle proposed four. (The word Aristotle uses, aition, "a responsible, explanatory factor" is not synonymous with the word cause in its modern sense.) These four causes are the
material cause, the matter out of which a thing is made;
the efficient cause, the source of motion, generation, or change;
the formal cause, which is the species, kind, or type;
and the final cause, the goal, or full development, of an individual, or the intended function of a construction or invention.
Examples:
Thus, a young lion is made up of tissues and
organs, its material cause;
the efficient cause is its parents, who generated it;
the formal cause is its species, lion;
and its final cause is its built-in drive toward becoming a mature
specimen.
In different contexts, while the causes are the same four, they apply
analogically. Thus, the material cause of a statue is the marble from
which it was carved;
the efficient cause is the sculptor;
the formal cause is the shape the sculptor realizedóHermes,
perhaps, or Aphrodite;
and the final cause is its function, to be a work of fine art.
The material cause is what anything is made of, for example,
brass or marble is the material cause of a given statue.
The formal cause is the form, type, or pattern according to
which anything is made;
thus, the style of architecture would be the formal cause of a
house.
The efficient cause is the immediate power acting to produce
the work, such as the manual energy of the laborers.
The final cause is the end or motive for the sake of which the
work is produced, that is, the pleasure of the owner.
In each context, Aristotle insists that something can be better
understood when its causes can be stated in specific terms rather
than in general terms. Thus, it is more informative to know that a
"sculptor" made the statue than to know that an "artist" made it; and
even more informative to know that "Polycleitus" chiseled it rather
than simply that a "sculptor" did so.
Aristotle thought his causal pattern was the ideal key for
organizing knowledge.
His lecture notes present impressive evidence of the power of this
scheme.
Rival Notions
In early modern philosophy, Aristotle's laws of causality were again challenged, resulting in two rival notions of cause.
The French philosopher and mathematician Renè Descartes and his school made cause identical with substance. The physical scientists often had a mechanical view of causality, reducing cause to a motion or change followed by other motion or change with a mathematical equality between measures of motion.
The British philosopher David Hume carried to a logical conclusion the contention of Sextus Empiricus that causality is not a real relation, but a fiction of the mind. To account for the origin of this fiction Hume used the doctrine of association.
Hume's explanation of cause led the German philosopher Immanuel Kant to posit cause as a fundamental category of understanding. Kant held that the only knowable objective world is the product of a synthetic activity of the mind. He accepted Hume's skeptical result as far as it concerned itself with the world of things-in-themselves. Dissatisfied, however, with the concept that experience is only a succession of perceptions without any discoverable relationship or coherence, Kant decided that causality is one of the principles of coherence obtaining in the world of phenomena, and that it is universally present there because thought, as part of its contribution to the nature of that world, always puts it there.
The British philosopher John Stuart Mill took up the problem at this point. He denied the fundamental postulate of Kant's transcendentalism, namely, that thought is responsible for the order of this world. Mill sought to justify belief in universal causation on empiricist principles; for him, a proposition is meaningful only if it describes what can be experienced.
Modern Directions
Along with the method of empiricism as the source of all knowledge
goes a definition of cause that is widely accepted today. The
cause of any event is a preceding event without which the event in
question would not have occurred. This is a mechanistic
view of causality popular in scientific circles. All the previous
events would constitute the complete cause.
Many philosophers deny the ultimate reality, or at least the
fundamental validity, of the causal relation.
Thus, the American philosopher Josiah Royce maintained that
the category of serial order, of which the category of cause is a
particular case, is itself subordinate to the ultimate category of
purpose.
The French philosopher Henri Bergson maintained that ultimate
reality or life is not bound by exact causal sequences. It is a
process of growth in which the unpredictable, and therefore the
uncaused, constantly occurs. No exact repetition happens in real
time; and where there is no repetition, there is no cause, for cause
means the antecedent that repeatedly is followed by the same
consequence.
... in philosophy, method of investigating the nature of truth by
critical analysis of concepts and hypotheses. One of the earliest
examples of the dialectical method was the Dialogues of Plato,
in which the author sought to study truth through discussion in the
form of questions and answers.
The term dialectic has both logical and metaphysical meanings in
philosophy. In logic, it generally refers to a process of critical
reasoning used either for refutation or for the discovery of
truth.
Plato conceived of dialectic primarily as question and answer, and as
the critical dialogue one has with one's soul. In the 18th century
KANT used the term dialectic
systematically in his CRITIQUE OF PURE REASON, arranging the four
contradictions of pure reason as four sets of thesis and antithesis.
For Hegel, dialectic is a
threefold process in which reason is revealed through reality, which
is both rational and spiritual in nature.
Aristotle thought
of dialectic as the search for the philosophic basis of science, and
he frequently used the term as a synonym for logic. In his logic,
Aristotle distinguished between dialectic and analytic.
Dialectic, he held, only tests opinions for their logical
consistency; analytic works deductively from principles resting on
experience and precise observation. This is clearly an intended break
with Plato's Academy, where dialectic was supposed to be the only
proper method for science and philosophy alike.
To the German philosopher Immanuel Kant,
dialectic meant the study of ultimate realities as distinguished from
objective phenomena.
Johann Gottlieb Fichte, followed by Friedrich Wilh. Joseph von
Schelling, applied the term synthesis to the third stage of resolving
the contradictions in the thesis and antithesis. This triadic
concept, which characterizes the usual meaning of the term
dialectic today, was advanced and elaborated by HEGEL
and MARX.
Dialectical materialism
Dialectical
materialism is the philosophical basis of
the works of Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels. The
so-called dialectical materialism of Karl Marx, frequently
considered to be a revision of the Hegelian system, asserts that the
material or objective universe exists independently of mind, which is
essentially a reflection of material reality. The materialist denies
transcendence and affirms the ultimate reality of the physical
world, beyond which nothing exists. Thus all phenomena, including
human behavior, are regarded as having their origins in the material
universe. Change is viewed as the result of the interaction of
opposites. Each thing that exists (thesis) gives rise to its opposite
(antithesis); the interaction of thesis and antithesis is ultimately
reconciled (synthesis) to become a new thesis. Marx and Engels used
these assumptions to analyze and explain historical development. They
saw human actions as motivated by the material, particularly the
economic, circumstances of the individual, and interpreted history as
the interaction of economic forces. According to Marx and Engels, the
19th-century's dialectic was the opposition of the BOURGEOISIE and
PROLETARIAT, which would lead to the ultimate synthesis, a classless
society.
ethnology
The science that analyzes and compares human cultures, as in social
structure, language, religion, and technology; cultural anthropology.
The branch of anthropology that deals with the origin, distribution,
and characteristics of the races of humankind.
(ethnos, people)
ethology
1. The scientific study of animal behavior, especially as it occurs
in a natural environment.
2. The study of human ethos and its formation.
(êthos, character)
Dada or Dadaism
...international nihilistic movement among European artists
and writers, 1916-22. It originated in Zürich with the French
poet Tristan Tzara and stressed absurdity and the role of the
unpredictable in artistic creation (Jean ARP, Max ERNST, Marcel
DUCHAMP, George GROSZ). The literary manifestations of Dada were
mostly nonsense poems-meaningless and random word combinations.